| Page 8 | Collège universitaire dominicain

Blog - Blogue

  • Analytics vs Continentals: the kayfabe of the 20th century

    jeudi 18 décembre 2014
    Iva Apostolova

     

    There are perhaps very few so vigorously re-fueled love-hate relationships in the history of philosophy as between the Analytics and the Continentals. It is not a secret that since its birth in 1900 Analytic Philosophy has acquired quite a reputation, a reputation that has created its own mythology (crossing both sides of the barricade, mind you; credit needs to be given where it’s deserved!). Fortunately, over the past few decades the analytic-continental blockade has begun to crack. Richard Rorty was one of the first few to do the unthinkable—openly and publicly cross the line from analytic to continental—and today Merleau-Ponty is on the tip of the tongue of many analytics.

    But for the first timer, here is a glimpse at some of the myths following the analytic tradition like a faithful shadow (leaving aside the fact that ‘analytic philosophy’ is an umbrella term huddling philosophers who do not want to be seen in the company of other ‘analytic’ philosophers. Strangely, Wittgenstein and his mentor Russell are the first that come to mind…)

    Myth 1: Analytic philosophy is dry: all it does is split hairs in an impossible jargon.

    Russell, one of the fathers of the analytic tradition, worried all his life (almost a century-long life!) about what he called the ‘unity of the proposition’. His main concern: how to analyze a meaningful philosophical proposition without actually losing its meaning. As for the jargon, well, if Kant’s ‘noumena’ and Heidegger’s 'Dasein' are not jargon, I don’t know what is! Inventing new vocabulary in the name of accuracy and depth is part and parcel of almost every philosopher’s agenda.

    Myth 2: Analytic philosophy doesn’t pay attention to the history of philosophy, it takes philosophical ideas out of context and analyzes them to death.

    Russell’s two-volume The History of Western Philosophy is still considered a must-read intro to philosophy. J. O. Urmson, a classically trained Oxford don, considered himself an Aristotle scholar before anything else.

    Myth 3: Analytic philosophers are boring and not interested in the meaning of life questions.

    William James, one of the great American Pragmatists and a major influence on the analytic tradition struggled with depression all his life. It is those struggles, as he himself admits, that pushed him into re-evaluating his own views on religious tolerance and truth. Truth, he thought, was the end of a thought ‘path’ in a stream of consciousness where the pen is as much a part of my experience as I am of the pen’s.

    And if you want philosophical excitement, you should read Wittgenstein’s Poker: The Story of a Ten-Minute Argument between Two Great Philosophers. Trust me, it’s worth your time!  

  • To read or not to read?

    vendredi 14 novembre 2014
    Iva Apostolova

     

    One thing can be said about philosophy without a doubt: it’s bulky. Have you seen the size of The Critique of Pure Reason by Kant?

    Yes, philosophers are verbose, and they also have a lot to say. Reading philosophical texts in a systematic way is a lot like learning a new language – at first there is the excitement of opening the door to a new world, then there is the pride of how much and how fast one is learning new vocabulary, and new ways of constructing one’s thoughts, until finally, panic and anxiety set in. Anxiety that no matter how much vocabulary one is acquiring, one can never ‘absorb’ and ‘engulf’ all of the new language.

    Even worse, soon after one starts reading literature or poetry in the newly acquired language, one realizes that all the fine nuances in the use and meaning of words, which are not to be found in dictionaries, are not only hard to catch but often completely lost on a reader who is outside the specific linguistic and cultural context. In other words, every language requires interpretation and re-interpretation, and every language is prone to misinterpretation. Imagine the same thing but turned up to the max and you’ve got a pretty accurate picture of how it feels to read philosophy.

    Because of its nature and its sheer volume, philosophy generates more anxiety compared to, perhaps, any other discipline.

    The question is how to deal with it.

    Like everything else in life, you try to create good habits that will carry you through.  

    Have you heard the expression: ‘the devil is in the details’? Well, that is especially true for philosophy. Perhaps the most important skill you learn in philosophy is connecting the dots, so to speak. It is not about how much you have read but whether you have managed to make the connections between the different ideas presented by the author/s. And that is hard! It is hard because every philosophical text is a complete, self-sufficient universe, a life narrative, if you will.   

    But there are things you can do to make the challenge manageable:

    Trust your instructors and mentors; they have been where you are now, and they know how you feel.

    Don’t forget that philosophy is dialogical in nature. In other words, it is far more important to bounce your ideas off someone else than lock yourself in the ‘armchair philosophy room’.

    Take an interest in something, a topic, a problem, or a dilemma, and stay with it.

    But take an interest in something that you can relate to. Despite common perception, philosophy is not, and should not be detached from one’s personal narrative. It doesn’t mean that you can’t change your mind about what interests you. All great philosophical minds have done it. But if you choose points of philosophical interest that you, as a person, can relate to, you will be able to connect the dots so much better, and eventually, weave a philosophical canvas which will become part of your own personal story.